Title:  Ts-201a1: Notes on Logic (BRA) - Diplomatic transcription [Draft]
 [Currently not available:]
Author:  Ludwig Wittgenstein
Editor:   Edited by
Organization: Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen (WAB). Editors: Alois Pichler, WAB (text and facsimile)
Funders & Partners:   Trinity College, Cambridge; Bertrand Russell Archives, Ontario; Oxford University Press, Oxford; Uni Research, Bergen; University of Bergen, Bergen; L. Meltzers Høyskolefond, Bergen; COST Action A32, Brussels; eContent+ DISCOVERY, Luxembourg; ICT PSP DM2E, Brussels
Transcription: Michael Biggs, Peter Cripps (transcription in MECS-WIT markup: No date)
Alois Pichler (2001-: coordination and editorial guidelines; amendments; conversion from MECS-WIT to XML-TEI; XML-TEI markup)
Claus Huitfeldt, Kjersti Bjørnestad Berg, Sindre Sørensen, MLCD project (2001: parser for conversion from MECS to XML)
Vemund Olstad, Øyvind L. Gjesdal (2002-: stylesheets)
Tone Merete Bruvik, Øyvind L. Gjesdal (2006-: XML-TEI validation)
Heinz Wilhelm Krüger, Deirdre C. P. Smith (2006-: amendments; XML-TEI markup)
Špela Vidmar (2013-14: proofreading)
Rights:  Copyright holders: The Master and Fellows of Trinity College, Cambridge; Bertrand Russell Archives at McMaster University Library, Hamilton, Ontario; University of Bergen, Bergen. Released under the Creative Commons General Public License Attribution, Non-Commercial, Share-Alike version 3 (CCPL BY-NC-SA).
Source description: Tba.

     
1
<Wittgenstein>
Summary
1
     

Summary


     
     The One reason for thinking the old notation wrong is that it is
very unlikely that from every proposition p an infinite number of
other propositions not-not-p, not-not-not-not-p, etc., should follow.
     
     If only th[e|o]se signs which contain proper names were complex
then propositions containing nothing but apparent variables would
be simple. Then what about their denials?
     
     The verb of a proposition cannot be “is true” or “is false”,
but whatever is true or false must already contain the verb.
     
     The [d|D]eductions only proceed according to the laws of deduction,
but these laws cannot justify the deduction.
     
     The One reason for supposing that not all propositions which have
more than one argument are relational propositions is that ˇif they
were, the relations of judgement and inference that would have to hold
between an arbitrary number of things.
     
     Every proposition which seems to be about a complex can be
analysed into a proposition about those ˇits cons[i|t]ituents and about
the proposition which describes a the complex perfectly; i.e., that
proposition which is equivalent to saying a the complex exists.
     
     The idea that propositions are names of complexes between L.W.
suggestionss L.W. that whatever is not a proper name is a sign for a
relation. Because spatial complexes * <ˇ* you – for instance imagine every fact as a
spatial complex.
>
consist of Things
& Relations only & the idea of a complex is taken
from spa

     

     In a proposition convert all its indefinables into variables;
there then remains a class of propositions which has is not all
propositions but a type.

2
     

     There are thus two ways in which signs are similar. The
names Socrates and Plato are similar: they are both names. But
whatever they have in common must not be introduced before Socrates
and Plato are introduced. The same applies to subject-predicate
form etc. Therefore, thing, proposition, subject-predicate form,
etc., are not indefinables, i.e., types are not indefinables.

     
     When we say a A judges is that etc., then we have to mention a
whole proposition which a A judges is. It will not do either to
mention only its constituents, or its constituents and form, but
not in the proper order. This shows that a proposition itself
must occur in the statement that it is judged; however, for
instance, “not-p” may be explained[.|,] p must occur in it. [t|T]he question, „What is negated” must have
a meaning


      Always a que[x|s]tion that is negated must have a meaning. Rott!

     
     To understand a proposition p it is not enough to know that
“udq.eudq;p implies ’“p“udq.eudq; is true, but we must also know that p also implies
“not-p” is false
~p implies “p is false”. This shows the ˇbipolarity of the proposition.
     
<W-F = Wahr-Falsch>
     To every molecular function ˇa [wf|WF] scheme corresponds. Therefore
we may use the [wf|WF] scheme itself instead of the function. Now
what the [wf|WF] scheme does is, it correlates the letters [w|W] and [f|F]
with each proposition. These two letters are the poles of atomic
propositions. Then ˇthe scheme correspondslates another [f|W] and [w|F] to these poles.
In this notation all that it matters is the correlation of the
outside poles to the pole of its ˇthe atomic propositions. Therefore
not-not-p is the same symbol as p. And Therefore we shall never get
two symbols for the same molecular functions.
3
     
     The meaning of a proposition is the fact which actually
corresponds to it.
     
     As the ab functions of atomic propositions are byi-polar
propositions again we can perform ab operations on them. We
[wi|sha]ll, b[e|y] doing so, correlate two new outside poles via the old
outside poles to the poles of the atomic propositions.
     

     The symbolising fact in a-p-b is that, say* a is on the
left of p and b on the right of p[,|;] then the correlation of new
poles is to be transitive, such so that ˇfor instance if a new pole a in whatever
way ˇi.e. via whatever poles is correlated to the inside a, the symbol is not changed
thereby. It is therefore possible to construct all possible ab
functions by performing one ab operation repeatedly, and we can
therefore talk of all ab functions as of all th[e|o]se functions which
can be obtained by performing this ab operation repeatedly. <ˇThis is quite arbitrary but if we such have fixed
on which sides the poles have to stand we must of
course stick to our convention. If for instance „apb”
says p then bpa says nothing. (It does not say
~p.) But a-apb-b is the same symbol as apb
(here the ab function vanishes automatically for here the new poles are
related to the same side of p as
the old ones. The question is always: how are the
new poles correlated to p compared with the way the
old poles are correlated to p.
>

     

      <[Note by B.R.]> [NB. ab means the same as [wf|WF], which means true-false.]


     
     Naming is like pointing. A function is like a line dividing
points ˇof a plane into right and left ones; then p or not-p has no meaning
because it does not divide [a|the] plane.
     
     But though a particular proposition “p“udq.eudq; or a “not-p“udq.eudq; has no
meaning, a general proposition for all p's, p or not-p“ has a
meaning because this does not contain [a|the] nonsensical function p
[n|o]r not-p but [a|the] function p or not-q“ just as for all x's
xRx contains the function xRy”.


4
     

     A proposition is a standard to which all facts behave, that with
names it ˇis otherwise; it is thenus byi-polarity and sense comes in;
just as one error arrow behaves to another error arrow by being in the same
sense or the opposite, so a fact behaves to a proposition.

     
     The form of a proposition has meaning in the following way.
Consider a symbol xRy. To symbols of this form correspond
couples of things whose names are respectively x and y. The
things x/y stand to one another in all sorts of relations, amongst
others some stand in the relatio[j|n] of R, and some not; just as I
single out a particular thing by a particular name I single out
all behaviours of the points x and y the one between with respect to the relation R.
of the other. I say that if an x stands in the relation of R
to a y the sign x of R y is to be called true to the fact and
otherwise false. This is a definition of sense.
     
<!>      In my theory p has the same meaning as not-p but opposite
snese. The meaning is the fact. The proper theory of judgment
must make it impossible to judge nonsense.
     
     It is not strictly true to say that we understand a
proposition p if we know that p is equivalent to “p is true”
for this would be the case if accidentally both were true or
false. What is wanted is the formal equivalence with respect
to the forms of the proposition[.|,] i.e., [A|a]ll the general
indefinables involved. The sense of an ab function of a proposition
is a function of its sense[:|.] [t|T]here are only unasserted propositions.
5
Assertion is merely psychological. Ifn not-p, ˇp is exactly the same
as if it stands alone; this point is absolutely fundamental. Among
the facts which make “p or q” true there are also facts which make “p
and q” true; if propositions do only mean ˇhave only meaning, we ought, to know ˇin such
a case, to say that these two propositions are identical, but in fact,
their sense is different for we have introduced sense by talking
of all p's and all q's. Consequently the molecular propositions
will only be used in cases where there ab function stands under
a generality sign or enters into another function such as I
believe that, etc., because then the sense enters.
     
     In “a judges p” p cannot be replaced by a proper name. This
appears if we substitute “a judges that p is true and not p is
false”. The proposition “a judges p” consists of the proper name a[.|,]
[T|t]he proposition p with its 2 poles, and a being related to both
of these poles in a certain way. This is obviously not the a
relation in the ordinary sense.
     
     The ab notation and for apparent variables makes it clear that
not and or are dependent on one another and we can therefore not
use them as simultaneous indefinables. | Some Same objections ˇin the case of app. var. to old
indefinables, [a|A]s as
ch in the case of molecular functions[,|:] [t|T]he application
of the ab notation to apparently- variable propositions becomes
clear if we consider that, for instance, the proposition for all
x, φx“ is to be true when φx is true for all x's and false
when φx is false for some x's. We see that some and all
occur simultaneously in the proper apparent variable notation.
6
     

     The Notation is:

for (x) φx; a ‒ (x) ‒ a φ x b ‒ ( x) ‒ b
and


for (φ x) φx : a ‒ (x) ‒ a φ x b ‒ (x) ‒ [v|b]

     
     Old definitions now become tautologous.
     

     In aRb it is not the complex that symbolises but the fact
that the symbol a stands in a certain relation to the symbol b.
Thus facts are symbolised by facts, or the more correctly: that
a certain thing is the case in the symbol says that a certain
thing is the case in the world.

     

     Judgment, question and command are all on the same level.
What interests logic in them is only the unasserted proposition.
Facts cannot be named.

     

     A proposition cannot occur in itself. This is the fundamental
truth of the theory of types.

     
     Every proposition that says something important indefinable about one
thing is a subject-predicate proposition, and so on.
     
     Therefore we can recognize a subject-predicate proposition
if we know it contains only one name and one form, etc. This
gives the construction of types. Hence the type of a proposition
can be recognized by its symbol alone.
7
     

     What is essential in a correct apparentˇ-variable notation is this:–
(1) it must mention a type of propositions; (2) it must show
which components of a proposition of this type are constants.

     

        [Components are forms and constituents.]

     
     Take (φ).φ!x. Then if we describe the kind of symbolschˇ, for which φ! stands
& which, by the above, is enough to determine the type, then
automatically “([x|φ]).φ!x” cannot be fi[ll|tt]ed by this descri[l|p]tion[.|,] be-
cause it contains „φ!x” & the
description is to describe all
that symbolizes in symbols
of the φ! – kind.
If the description
is thus complete vicious circles
can just as little occur as
if for instance in (φ).φ(x) (φ).(x)φ (where
(x)φ is a subject-predicat prop)
































1
     

Wittgenstein
First MS.
     
Indefinables are of two sorts: names, & forms. Propositions cannot
consist of names alone; they cannot be classes of names. A name
can not only occur in two different propositions, but can occur in the
same way in both.
     
       Propositions [which are symbols having reference to facts] are
themselves facts: that this inkpot is on this table may express
that I sit in this chair.
     
       It can never express the common characteristic of two
objects that we denote designate them by the same name but by two different
ways of designation, for, since names are arbitrary, we might
<also> choose different names, & where then would be the common
element in the designations? Nevertheless one is always tempted,
in a difficulty, to take refuge in different ways of designation.
     
       Frege said “propositions are names”; Russell said
“propositions correspond to complexes”. Both are false; & especially
false is the statement “propositions are names of complexes”.
     
       It is easy to suppose that only such symbols are complex as contain
names of objects objects, & ˇthat accordingly “(∃x,φ).φx” or “(∃x,ˇR,y).xRy” must be
simple. It is then natural to call the first of these the name of a form,
the second the name of a relation. But in that case what is the meaning
of (e.g.) “~(∃x,y).xRy”? Can we put “not” before a name?
2
     

Wittg. –


       The reason why “~Socrates” means nothing is that “~x” does
not express a property of x.
     
       There are positive & negative facts: if the proposition “this rose is not
red” is true, then its ˇwhat it signifies is negative. But the occurrence of the
word “not” does not indicate this unless we know that the
signification of ˇthe proposition “this rose is red” (when it is true) is positive. It is
only from both, the negation & the negated proposition, that we can
conclude to a characteristic of the significance of the whole proposition.
(We are not here speaking of negations of general propositions, i.e.
of such as contain apparent variables.) Negative facts only justify
the negations of simpl atomic propositions.)
     
       Positive & negative facts there are, but not true &
false facts.
     
       If we overlook the fact that propositions have a sense which
is independent of their truth or falsehood, it easily seems as if
true & false were two equally justified relations between the sign
& what is signified. (We might then say e.g. that “qsignifies
in the true way what “not-q” signifies in the false way). But
are not true & false in fact equally justified? Could we not express
ourselves by means of false propositions just as well as hitherto with
true ones, so long as we know that they are meant falsely?
3
No! For a proposition is then true when it is as we assert in this
proposition; & accordingly if by “q” we mean “not-q”, & it is as we
mean to assert, then in the new interpretation “q” is actually true
& not false. But it is important that we can mean the same
by “q” as by “not-q”, for it shows that neither to the symbol
“not” nor to the manner of its combination with “q” does a
characteristic of the denotation of “q” correspond.





























4
     

2nd MS.
     
We must be able to understand propositions which we have never heard
before. But every proposition is a new symbol. Hence we must have
general indefinable symbols; these are unavoidable if propositions are not
all indefinable.
     
       Whatever corresponds in reality to compound propositions must not be
more than what corresponds to their several atomic propositions.
     
       Not only must logic not deal with [particular] things, but just as
little with relations & predicates.
     
       There are no propositions containing real variables.
     
       What corresponds in reality to a proposition depends upon whether it is
true or false. But we must be able to understand a proposition without
knowing if it is true or false.
     
       What we know when we understand a proposition is this: We know
what is the case if the proposition is true, & what is the case if it is false.
But we do not know [necessarily] whether it is true or false.
     
       Propositions are not names.
     
       We can never distinguish one logical type from another by
attributing a property to members of the one which we deny to members of
the other.
     
       Symbols are not what they seem to be. In “aRb”, “R” looks
like a substantive, but is not one. What symbolizes in “aRb” is
that R occurs between a & b. Hence “R” is not the indefinable
in “aRb”. Similarly in “φx”, “φ” looks like a substantive
but is not one; in “~p”, “~” looks like “φ” but is not like it.
This is the first thing that indicates that there may not be logical constants.
A reason against them is the generality of logic: logic cannot treat a
special set of things.
5
     

Wittg.–

       Molecular propositions contain nothing beyond what is contained in their
atoms; they add no material information above that contained in their
atoms.
     
       All that is essential about molecular functions is their T-F schema
[i.e. the statement of the cases when they are true & the cases when they are false].
     
       Alternative indefinability shows that the indefinables have not
been reached.
     
       Every proposition is essentially true-false: to understand it, we
must know both what must be the case if it is true, & what must be
the case if it is false. Thus a proposition has two poles, corresponding
to the case of its truth & the case of its falsehood. We call this the
sense of a proposition.
     
       In regard to notation, it is important to note that not every
feature of a symbol symbolizes. In two molecular functions which have
the same T-F schema, what symbolizes must be the same. In
“not-not-p”, “not-p” does not occur; for “not-not-p” is the same
as “p”, & therefore, if “not-p” occurred in “not-not-p”, it would
occur in “p”.
     
       Logical indefinables cannot be predicates or relations, because
propositions, owing to sense, cannot have predicates or relations. Nor are
“not” & “or”, like judgment, analogous to predicates or relations,
because they do not introduce anything new.
     
       Propositions are always complex even if they contain no names.
6
     
       A proposition must be understood when all its indefinables are understood.
The indefinables in “aRb” are introduced as follows:
       “a” is indefinable;
       “b” is indefinable;
        Whatever “x” & “y” may mean, “xRy” says something
indefinable about their meanings.
     
       A complex symbol must never be introduced as a single indefinable.
(Thus e.g. no proposition is indefinable.) For if one of its parts occurs
also in another connection, it must there be re-introduced. And would
it then mean the same?
     
       The ways by which we introduce our indefinables must permit us
to construct all propositions that have sense [? meaning] from these
indefinables alone. It is easy to introduce “all” & “some” in
a way that will make the construction of (say) “(x,y).xRy”
possible from “all” & “xRy” as introduced before.















7
     

Wittg.–
3rd MS.
     
A comparis An analogy for the theory of truth: Consider a black patch on
white paper; then we can describe the form of the patch by mentioning, for
each point of the surface, whether it is white or black. To the fact that a
point is black corresponds a positive fact, to the fact that a point is
white (not black) corresponds a negative fact. If I designate a
point of the surface (one of Frege's “truth-values”), this is as if I set up an
assumption to be decided upon. But in order to be able to say of a point
that it is black or that it is white, I must first know when a point is
to be called black & when it is to be called white. In order to be
able to say that “p” is true (or false), I must first have
determined under what circumstances I call a proposition true,
& thereby I determine the sense of a proposition. The point [on|in] which the
analogy depends fails is this: I can indicate a point of the paper what is
white & black, but to a proposition without sense nothing corresponds,
for it does not designate a thing (truth-value), whose
properties might be called “false” or “true”; the verb of a
proposition is not “is true” or “is false”, as Frege believes,
but what is true must already contain the verb.
     
       The comparison of language & reality is like that of retinal image & visual
image: to the blind spot nothing in the visual image seems to correspond,
& thereby the boundaries of the blind spot determine the visual image – as
true negations of atomic propositions determine reality.
8
     

Wittg.–

       Logical inferences can, it is true, be made in accordance with
Frege's or Russell's laws of deduction, but this cannot justify the inference;
& therefore they are not primitive propositions of logic. If p follows from
q, it can also be inferred from q, & the “manner of deduction”
is indifferent.
     
       Those symbols which are called propositions in which “variables
occur” are in reality not propositions at all, but only schemes of
propositions, which only become propositions when we replace the
variables by constants. There is no proposition which is expressed
by “x = x”, for “x” has no signification; but there is a proposition
“(x).x = x” & propositions such as “Socrates = Socrates” etc.
     
       In books on logic, no variables ought to occur, but only the general
propositions which justify the use of variables. It follows that the
so-called definitions of logic are not definitions, but only schemes of
definitions, & instead of these we ought to put general propositions;
& similarly the so-called primitive ideas ˇ(Urzeichen) of logic are not primitive
ideas, but the schemes of them. The mistaken idea that there are
things called facts or complexes & relations easily leads to the opinion
that there must be a relation of questioning to the facts, & then the question
arises whether a relation can hold between an arbitrary number of things,
since a fact can follow from arbitrary cases. It is a fact that the proposition
which e.g. expresses that q follows from p & p ⊃ q is this: p.p ⊃ q. ⊃ p.q.q.
9
     

Wittg.–

       At a pinch, one is tempted to interpret “not-p” as
“everything else, only not p”. That from a single fact p an
infinity of others, not-not-p etc., follow, is hardly credible.
Man possesses an innate capacity for constructing symbols with
which some sense can be expressed, without having the
slightest idea what each word signifies. The best example of
this is mathematics, for man has until lately used the
symbols for numbers without knowing what they signify or
that they signify nothing.
     
       Russell's “complexes” were to have the useful property of being compounded,
& were to combine with this the agreeable property that they could be
treated as ˇlike “simples”. But this alone made them unserviceable as
logical types, since there would have been significance in asserting,
of a simple, that it was complex. But a property cannot be a
logical type.
     
       Every statement about apparent complexes can be resolved into the
logical sum of a statement about the constituents & a statement
about the proposition which describes the complex completely. How,
in each case, the resolution is to be made, is an important
question, but its answer is not unconditionally necessary for the
construction of logic.
10
     

Wittg.–

       That “or” & “not” etc. are not relations in the same sense
as “right” & “left” etc., is obvious to the plain man. The possibility
of cross-definitions in the old logical indefinables shows, of itself,
that these are not the right indefinables, &, even more conclusively,
that they do not denote relations.
     
       If we change a constituent a of a proposition φ(a) into a
variable, then there is a class
^
p
{(∃x).φ(x) = p}.
This class in general still depends upon what, by an arbitrary convention,
we have mean by “φ(x)”. But if we change into variables all
those symbols whose significance was arbitrarily determined, there is
still such a class. But this is now not dependent upon any convention,
but only upon the nature of the symbol “φ(x)”. It corresponds
to a logical type.
     
       Types can never be distinguished from each other by saying (as is often
done) that one has th[i|e]s<e> but the other has th[at|ose] propert[y|i]<es>, for this presupposes
that there is a meaning in asserting all these properties of both types. But
from this it follows that, at best, these properties may be types, but certainly
not the objects of which they are asserted.
11
     

Wittg.–

       At a pinch, we are always inclined to explanations of ˇlogical functions of
propositions which ˇaim at introducing into the function either only contain the constituents of these propositions,
or only their forms, etc. etc; & we overlook that ordinary language
would not contain the whole propositions if it did not need them:
However, e.g., “not-p” may be explained, there must always be
a meaning given to the question “what is denied?”
     
       The very possibility of Frege's explanations of “not-p” &
“if p then q”, from which it follows that not-not-p denotes
the same as p, makes it probable that there is some method of
designation in which “not-not-p” corresponds to the same
symbol as “p”. But if this method of designation suffices for
logic, it must be the right one.
     
       Names are points, sentences propositions arrows – they have sense. The
sense of a proposition is determined by the two poles true & false.
The form of a proposition is like a straight line, which divides all
points of a plane into right & left. The line does this automatically,
the form of proposition only by convention.
12
     

Wittg.–

       Just as little as we are concerned, in logic, with the relation of a
name to its meaning, just so little are we concerned with the
relation of a proposition to reality, but we want to know the
meaning of names & the sense of propositions – as we
introduce an indefinable concept “A” by saying: “‘A’ denotes
something indefinable”, so we introduce e.g. the form of propositions
aRb by saying: “For all meanings of “x” & “y”, “xRy”
expresses something indefinable about x & y”.
     
       In place of every proposition “p”, let us write
a
b
p”. Let every
correlation of propositions to each other or of names to propositions
be effected by a correlation of their poles “a” & “b”. Let this
correlation be transitive. Then accordingly “
a ‒ a
b ‒ b
p” is the same
symbol as “
a
b
p”. Let n propositions be given. I then call a
“class of poles” of these propositions every class of n members, of which
each is a pole of one of the n propositions, so that one member corresponds
to each proposition. I then correlate with each class of poles one of two
poles (a & b). The sense of the symbolizing fact thus constructed I
cannot define, but I know it.
     
       If p = not-not-p etc., this shows that the traditional method of
symbolism is wrong, since it allows a plurality of symbols with the same
sense; & thence it follows that, in analyzing such propositions, we
must not be guided by Russell's method of symbolizing.
13
     

Wittg.–

       It is to be remembered that names are not things, but classes:
“A” is the same letter as “A“. This has the most important
consequences for every symbolic language.
     
       Neither the sense nor the meaning of a proposition is a thing. These
words are incomplete symbols.
     
       It is impossible to dispense with propositions in which the same
argument occurs in different positions. It is obviously useless to
replace φ(a,a) by φ(a,b).a = b.
     
       Since the ab-functions of p are again bi-polar propositions, we
can form ab-functions of them, & so on. In this way a series of
propositions will arise, in which in general the symbolizing facts will
be the same in several members. If now we find an ab-function of such
a kind that by repeated application of it every ab-function can be
generated, then we can define introduce the totality of ab-functions as the totality of
those that are generated by application of this function. Such a function is ~p ⌵ ~q.















14
     

Wittg.–

       It is easy to suppose a contradiction in the fact that on the one hand
all every possible complex proposition is a simple ab-function of simple
propositions, & that on the other hand the repeated application of one
ab-function suffices to generate all these propositions. If e.g. an
affirmation can be generated by double negation, is negation in any
sense contained in affirmation? Does “p” deny “not-p” or assert “p”,
or both? And how do matters stand with the definition of “ ⊃ ” by
“ ⌵ ” & “~” “.”, or of “ ⌵ ” by “.” & “ ⊃ ”? And how e.g. shall
we introduce p|q (i.e. ~p ⌵ ~q), if not by saying that this
expression says something indefinable about all arguments p & q?
But the ab-functions must be introduced as follows: The function
p|q is merely a mechanical instrument for constructing all possible
symbols of ab-functions. The symbols arising by repeated application
of the symbol “|” do not contain the symbol “p|q”. We need a rule
according to which we can form all symbols of ab-functions, in order
to be able to speak of the class of them; & we now speak of them e.g. as
those symbols of functions which can be generated by repeated application
of the operation “|”. And we say now: For all p's & q's, “p|q” says
something indefinable about the sense of those simple propositions
which are contained in p & q.
15
     

Wittg.–

       The assertion-sign is logically quite without significance. It ˇonly shows, in
Frege & Whitehead & Russell, that these authors hold the propositions so
indicated to be true. “⊢” therefore belongs as little to the proposition as
(say) the number of the proposition. A proposition cannot possibly assert
of itself that it is true.
     
       Every right theory of judgment must make it impossible for me
to judge that this table penholders the book. Russell's theory does not
satisfy this requirement.
     
       It is clear that we understand propositions without knowing whether
they are true or false. But we can only know the meaning of a proposition
when we know if it is true or false. What we understand is the sense
of the proposition.
     
       The assumption of the existence of logical objects makes it
appear remarkable that ˇin the sciences propositions of the form “p[or| ]q”, “ p ⊃ q”,
etc. ˇare only then not provisional when “ ⌵ ” &” ⊃ ” stand within the
scope of a generality-sign [apparent variable].















16
     

Wittg.–
4th MS.
     
If we formed all possible atomic propositions, the world would be completely
described if we declared the truth or falsehood of each. [I doubt this.]
     
       The chief characteristic of my theory is that, in it, p has the same
meaning as not-p.
     
       A false theory of relations makes it easily seem as if the relation
of fact & constituent were the same as that of fact & fact which follows
from it. But the similarity of the two may be expressed thus: φa. ⊃ .φ,a a = a.
     
       If a word creates a world so that in it the principles of logic
are true, it thereby creates a world in which the whole of mathematics holds;
& similarly it could not create a world in which a proposition was
true, without creating its constituents.
     
       Signs of the form “p ⌵ ~p” are senseless, but not the proposition
“(p).p ⌵ ~p”. If I know that this rose is either red or not red, I
know nothing. The same holds of all ab-functions.
     
       To understand a proposition means to know what is the case
if it is true. Hence we can understand it without knowing if it is true.
We understand it when we understand its constituents & forms.
If we know the meaning of “a” & “b”, & if we know what “xRy”
means for all x's & y's, then we also understand “aRb”.
     
       I understand the proposition “aRb” when I know that either the fact that
aRb or the fact that not aRb corresponds to it; but this is not to be
confused with the false opinion that I understand “aRb” when I know that
“aRb or not-aRb” is the case.
17
     

Wittg.–

       But the form of a proposition symbolizes in the following way: Let us
consider symbols of the form “xRy”; to these correspond primarily pairs of
objects, of which one has the name “x”, the other the name “y”. The x's & y's
stand in various relations to each other, among others the relation R holds
between some, but not between others. I know now determine the sense
of “xRy” by laying down: when the facts behave in regard to “xRy”
so that the meaning of “x” stands in the relation R to the meaning of “y”,
then I say that they [the facts] are “of like sense” [“gleichsinnig”] with
the proposition “xRy”; otherwise, “of opposite sense” [entgegengesetzt”];
I correlate the facts to the symbol “xRy” by thus dividing them into
those of like sense & those of opposite sense. To this correlation corresponds
the correlation of name & meaning. Both are psychological. Thus I
understand the form “xRy” when I know that it discriminates the
behaviour of x & y according as these stand in the relation R or not.
In this way I extract from all possible relations the relation R,
as, by a name, I extract its meaning from among all possible things.
     

       Strictly speaking, it is incorrect to say: We understand the proposition
p when we know that ‘“p” is true’ ≡ p; for this would naturally always
be the case if accidentally the propositions to right & left of the symbol “≡”
were both true or both false. We require not only an equivalence, but a
formal equivalence, which is bound up with the introduction of the
form of p.
     
       The sense of an ab-function of p is a function of the sense of p.
18
     

Wittg.–

       The ab-functions use the discrimination of facts, which their
arguments bring forth, in order to generate new discriminations.
     
       Only facts can express sense, a class of names cannot.
This is easily shown.
     
       There is no thing which is the form of a proposition, & no
name which is the name of a form. Accordingly we can also
not say that a relation which in certain cases holds between
things holds sometimes between forms & things. This goes
against Russell's theory of judgment.
     
       It is ˇvery easy to forget that, tho' the propositions of a form
can be either true or false, each one of these propositions can only
be either true or false, not both.
     
       Among the facts which make “p or q” true, there are some
which make “p & q” true; but the class which makes “p or q” true
is different from the class which makes “p & q” true; & ˇonly this is what
matters. For we introduce this class, as it were, when we introduce
ab-functions.
     
       A very natural objection to the way in which I have introduced e.g. propositions
of the form xRy is that by it propositions such as (∃x,y).xRy & similar ones
are not explained, which yet obviously have in common with aRb what
cRd has in common with aRb. But when we introduced propositions of the form
xRy we mentioned no one particular proposition of this form; & we only need to
introduce (∃x,y).φ(x,y) for all φ's in any way which makes the sense of these
propositions dependent on the sense of all propositions of the form φ(a,b), & thereby the
justification of our procedure is proved.
19
     
Wittg.–

       The indefinables of logic must be independent of each other. If an indefinable
is introduced, it must be introduced in all combinations in which it can occur.
We cannot therefore introduce it first for one combination, then for another;
e.g., if the form xRy has been introduced, it must henceforth be
understood in propositions of the form aRb just in the same way as in
propositions such as (∃x,y).xRy & others. We must not introduce it
first for one class of cases, then for the other; for it would remain doubtful if
its meaning was the same in both cases, & there would be no ground for
using the same manner of combining symbols in both cases. In short, for
the introduction of indefinable symbols & classes combinations of symbols the same holds,
mutatis mutandis, that Frege has said for the introduction of symbols
by definitions.
     
       It is a priori likely that the introduction of atomic propositions is
fundamental for the understanding of all other kinds of propositions.
In fact the understanding of general propositions obviously depends on
that of atomic propositions.
     
       Cross-definability in the realm of general propositions leads to the
quite similar questions to those in the realm of ab-functions.









20
     

Wittg.–

       When we say “A believes p”, this sounds, it is true, as if here
we could substitute a proper name for “p”; but we can see that here
a sense, not a meaning, is concerned, if we say “A believes that
p’ is true”; & in order to make the direction of p even more
explicit, we might say “A believes that ‘p’ is true & ‘not-p’ is false”.
Here the bi-polarity of p is expressed, & it seems that we shall only
be able to express the proposition “A believes p” correctly by the
ab-notation; say by making “A” have a relation to the poles “a”
& “b” of a-p-b.
The epistemological
questions concerning the nature of judgment & belief cannot be solved
without a correct apprehension of the form of the proposition.
     
       The ab-notation shows the dependence of or & not, & thereby
that they are not to be employed as simultaneous indefinables.
     
       Not: “The complex sign ‘aRb’” says that a stands in the
relation R to b; but that ‘a’ stands in a certain relation to ‘b’
says that aRb.
     
       In philosophy there are no deductions: it is purely descriptive.
     
       Philosophy gives no pictures of reality.
     
       Philosophy can neither confirm nor confute scientific investigation.
21
     

Wittg.–

       Philosophy consists of logic & metaphysics: logic is its basis.
     
       Epistemology is the philosophy of psychology.
     
       Distrust of grammar is the first requisite for philosophizing.
     
       Propositions can never be indefinables, for they are always complex.
That also words like “ambulo” are complex appears in the fact that
their root with a different termination gives a different sense.
     
       Only the doctrine of general indefinables permits us to
understand the nature of functions. Neglect of this doctrine leads
to an impenetrable thicket.
     
       Philosophy is the doctrine of the logical form of scientific
propositions (not only of primitive propositions).
     
       The word “philosophy” ought always to designate
something over or under, but not beside, the natural sciences.
     
       Judgment, ˇcommand & question [&|a]ll stand on the same level; but
all have in common the propositional form, which does interests us.
     
       The construction structure of the sentence proposition must be recognized, the
rest comes of itself. But ordinary language conceals the
structure of the proposition: in it, relations look like predicates,
predicates like names, etc.
     
       Facts cannot be named.
22
     

Wittg.–

       It is easy to suppose that “individual”, “particular”, “complex”
etc. are primitive ideas of logic. Russell e.g. says “individual”
& “matrix” are “primitive ideas”. This error presumably
is to be explained by the fact that, by employment of variables
instead of ˇthe generality-signs, it comes to seem as if logic dealt
with things which have been deprived of all properties except
thing-hood, & with propositions deprived of all properties except
complexity. We forget that the indefinables of symbols [Urbilder
von Zeichen] only occur under the generality-sign, never outside it.
     
       Just as people used to struggle to bring all propositions into the
subject-predicate form, so now it is natural to conceive every
proposition as expressing a relation, which is just as incorrect.
What is justified in this desire is fully satisfied by Russell's theory
of manufactured relations.
     
       One of the most natural attempts at solution consists in
regarding “not-p” as “the opposite of p”, where then “opposite” would be
the indefinable relation. But it is easy to see that every such attempt
to replace the ab-functions by descriptions must fail.
23
     
Wittg.–

       The false assumption that propositions are names leads us to
believe that there must be logical objects: for the meanings of logical
propositions will have to be such things.
     
       A correct explanation of logical propositions must give them a unique
position as against all other propositions.
     
       No proposition can say anything about itself, because the symbol
of the proposition cannot be contained in itself; this must be the
basis of the theory of logical types.
     
       Every proposition which says something indefinable about a
thing is a subject-predicate proposition; every proposition which
says something indefinable about two things expresses a dual relation
between these things, & so on. Thus every proposition which contains
only one name & one indefinable form is a subject-predicate
proposition, & so on. An indefinable simple sign symbol can only be a
name, & therefore we can know, by the symbol of an atomic
proposition, whether it is a subject-predicate proposition.